Saturday, 24 January 2015 14:54

Usury, Social Credit, and Catholicism

Rate this item
(1 Vote)

As I tried to show in my recent blog entry on “Social Credit and Usury”, the claim that usury, defined as the charging of interest on loans, is THE problem and that Social Credit means nothing more than “usury-free money” is a serious but all too common misrepresentation of the Social Credit diagnosis and remedial proposals.

Unfortunately, some people, upon learning that the banks create the money that they lend out of nothing, never recover from their initial shock so as to look at anything deeper.

It is certainly true that, under the existing system, the banks are not upfront – as they should be – about their money-creation activities. Whenever we take out a loan, for example, we are not provided with an opportunity to give informed consent. No one signs a release form stating “Do you clearly understand that the money that is being lent to you is created out of nothing by the bank and does not consist in hard-earned dollars that are being borrowed from some other depositor (who must now have to do without them so long as they remain on loan)?”

It is also true that, partially on account of the smokescreen that the banks are lending other people’s hard-earned money, the charges which the banks levy under the existing system can be and often are onerous, excessive, and/or exploitative for one reason or another.

But these negative aspects of the present financial system are symptoms or consequences of a more fundamental problem, rather than constituting, in and of themselves, the heart of the evil.

The root of the economic problem is not to be found in the mere fact that the private banks create the bulk of the money supply ex nihilo, nor in the mere fact that they then proceed to charge interest on the monies that they loan out. The root of the economic problem has to do with policy. The financial system serves the wrong policy. Instead of facilitating to the greatest possible extent the efficient delivery of those goods and services that people can use with profit to themselves, the conventional financial system centralizes wealth, power, and privilege in the hands of those who have acquired monopoly control over financial credit. The policy which the private banks currently administer is a self-serving policy in lieu of what might be termed common policy: that policy which would serve the best interests of each citizen.[1]

It is crucial for people to understand that, apart from any question of profiteering or exploitation on the part of the banks, the financial system does not adequately reflect reality. As a result of existing banking and cost accountancy conventions, there is not enough producer credit to catalyze the production of all of the goods and services that people can use with profit to themselves and there is not enough consumer income liberated in the course of their production so as to purchase all of the goods and services that do arrive on the market and to liquidate all of their costs. This artificial scarcity of credit relative to the purposes independently determined by consumers is THE fundamental flaw of the existing system. Cf. Social Credit: A Simple (If Somewhat Lengthy) Explanation .

For this reason, eliminating the private creation of credit and the charging of interest would not, by themselves, guarantee that the financial system would operate in full service to the common individual. Indeed, one can imagine an interest-free system in which money-creation and its issuance, having been completely centralized in the hands of the state, is used to impose policy in every field of human activity (economic, political, and cultural) for the benefit of a ruling oligarchy. Such a financial system would be even more despotic and tyrannical than the existing one. If we do not wish to fall into the fire after having spent many centuries in the frying pan, our monetary reform efforts should be more concerned with achieving real or concrete individual benefit for all of the citizens of a country, rather than with doing damage to private banking.

This is not to say that usury – most broadly and properly defined as ‘dishonest profit’ in any form – is not a feature of the existing system or does not merit our concern. Any illegitimate transfer of wealth, power, and privilege from the common consumer to the proprietors of the banking system may be classified as a type of ‘usury’.[2] It is precisely usury understood in this sense which allows for the centralization of economic benefits under the existing financial regime. Douglas’ opposition to any and all forms of illegitimate transfer, as well as to the anti-social policy which underlies it, is on record for all to see:

The Anti-Social Character of the Reigning Financial Policy:

Finance has the power to impose a policy on the public, even if that policy is demonstrably anti-public in character.[3]

[T]he banks are so-called private institutions which administer this collective credit for their own ends, and those ends are by no means similar to the ends of the community of individuals from whom the credit takes its rise.[4]

[W]e have to realise that there exists, and is being exercised for anti-social purposes, a monopoly of the ticket supply....[5]

The modern State is an unlimited liability corporation, of which the citizens are the workers and guarantors, and the financial system the beneficiary.[6]

 

The Illegitimate Transfer of Purchasing Power

As the situation stands at present, the banker is in an unique position. He is probably the only known instance of the possibility of lending something without parting with anything, and making a profit on the transaction, obtaining in the first instance his commodity free.[7]

[T]he root of the evil accruing from the system is in the constant filching of purchasing power from the individual in favour of the financier....[8]

Banking, as it is presently operated, is:
“the most colossal lucrative fraud that has ever been perpetrated on society.”[9]

[T]he essential power which the banks have acquired is the power of the monetization and demonetization of real wealth. That is to say, the power of creating acceptable and accepted orders or demands upon the producing system and of destroying them on recall; and the essence of their fraud upon civilization is not in the magnificent technique of the system which they employ [i.e., creating money out of nothing - OH], or even in the charges which they make for the use of this money which they create, even though these charges, i.e., their interest rates, may be considered in many cases exorbitant.

The essence of the fraud is the claim that the money that they create is their own money, and the fraud differs in no respect in quality but only in its far greater magnitude, from the fraud of counterfeiting. At the instigation of the banking system, barbarously severe penalties are imposed upon the counterfeiter of a ten-shilling note, but a peerage is conferred upon the counterfeiter by banking methods of sums running into hundreds of millions. [10]

The banking system ... is the core of the monetary problem, and when I say this I particularly want you to avoid making the mistake of assuming that it is the profits of the banking system which I am attacking. I think these profits are exorbitant, but they are quite unimportant in comparison with the disastrous effects of the system itself which the bankers operate.[11]


Mr. Murdoch – “You think it is a fair thing to dip into the reserves and profits of these banks and in a
sense confiscate them?”

Major Douglas – “I do not think it is a question of confiscation at all. There is a Spanish proverb which says, ‘He who robs a robber earns a hundred year’s remission.’ and I regard these undisclosed assets and many other assets as being quite unjustifiable.”[12]

Before, then, each of the factories in the above illustration could commence operation, it had to be built and equipped with machinery. There are two methods by which this operation could have been financed. The first is that it could have been financed out of savings, the method commonly suggested by orthodox financial authorities as that by which capital expenditure is financed. It is very questionable whether much modern finance is done this way. ...

From the ordinary point of view, the people who put up the money are legitimately entitled not only to a profit on this money, but also to get it back again in full, since in their case the money may be assumed to represent past effort, so that the factories in question must make a charge on each article turned out which will provide the money to meet these claims. The only objection to this perfectly fair assumption is that, in the aggregate, the public have not got the money.

The second method, and probably the method by which most modern financing is done, under cover of a smoke screen provided by comparatively small subscriptions from the public, is that some financial institution actually creates the money, taking debentures on the new factories as security. Ethically, there is every difference between money created by a stroke of the pen and money acquired as the result of years of effort, but I am not at the moment concerned with ethics. ... Secondly, there is no provision in this method of financing for the money required to pay the interest on the debentures, which, in fact, can only be paid, if it is paid, by the issue of fresh money to pay it, which, under existing circumstances, comes from the same source, that is to say, the financial system. From this point of view, it is the difference between usury and profit – a difference clearly drawn in the Middle Ages.[13]

Stripped of its complications, the fact emerges that we live under a system not at all dissimilar to that of a commercial company with unlimited liability in which new debentures are constantly being issued and allocated free of charge to the financial system and its controllers, who take no risks and do no creative work. The general population is fundamentally in the position of wage earners, and the taxation upon them goes to pay the interest on these mortgage debentures. The income-tax authorities are in the position of accountants, and debt collectors acting in the interest of the debenture holders.[14]

When the history of these times comes to be written, it will be regarded as almost incredible that the population of this or any other country making any claims to civilisation should have permitted the continuous levy in favour of financial institutions which now passes under the name of “taxation”.[15]

If the present system of taxation consisted, as it does, of an organized system of robbery but without any other objectionable aspects, it would, in all conscience, be unjustified.[16]

 

The Illegitimate Transfer of Ownership

The momentum of business induces business undertakings to carry on to a point considerably beyond that justified by their unmortgaged liquid resources, even assuming that their transactions have been financed normally in this way. As a result of this, and as indeed might be expected from the control over the money system acquired by the banking institutions, it is probably true to say that in Great Britain, 90 percent of trade and business has come into the possession or control of banking interests. Such a tremendous transfer of ownership has probably never occurred in recorded history.[17]

May I make this point clear beyond all doubt? It is the claim to the ownership of money which is the core of the matter. Any person or any organization who can create practically at will sums of money equivalent to the price values of all the goods produced by the community is the virtual owner of those goods, and, therefore, the claim of the banking system to the ownership of the money which it creates is a claim to the ownership of the country.[18]

 

The Illegitimate Transfer of Control over Policy

[T]here is always a deficit of available purchasing power. This deficit has to be met to a greater or less extent, so that the process may go on; and the making up of the deficit by the creation of loans is, of course, the chief business of the banking system; it is the business by which ultimately the whole of every country – its industries, its loans, its institutions – (I am endeavouring to use the most conservative phrases) – must mathematically go into the control of the financial institutions, since they alone have the possibility of meeting these deficits in purchasing power which sooner or later must occur in every business relationship.[19]

Now by a convention, the origin of which goes back into the mists of antiquity, a debtor is the servant of his creditor until his debt is repaid, and since the banking system is the origin of modern money and never gives money, but always lends it, and since under our modern money economy we are all of us obliged to have the use of money, we are quite indisputably all of us directly or indirectly the servants of the banks. ... I feel sure you will agree without further argument that money at the present time is our master, and not our servant.[20]

Now it must be obvious that this process gives those in control of it absolute control of the economic situation, and what is perhaps of even greater importance, this control is fundamentally dependent on a scarcity of money, and consequently of purchasing power. Individuals must use economic products, and they can only obtain those economic products by the means of money. If they are short of money, terms on which they obtain money can be imposed upon them; if they are not short of money those terms cannot be imposed. And it therefore follows that the existence of a money control necessitates a condition of economic scarcity, quite irrespective of the advances of scientific progress or productive capacity, and restricts economic production within the limits imposed by restricted money demand.[21]

 

Even so, Douglas did not focus his attention or the thrust of his reforming efforts on the question of usury because usury is not the root cause of the macro-economic gap between prices and incomes (N.B., the financing and accounting of real capital under existing conventions accounts for the bulk of the gap; profits derived from interest are merely an exacerbating factor) and the implementation of the Social Credit remedial measures are likely, all by themselves, to do away with much of the onerous, excessive, and/or exploitative conditions that are often associated with the charging of interest as it is currently practised.

Under the existing system, interest charges and other fees typically bear no linear connection to operating costs and are determined instead (within whatever regulations may have been imposed by a government or a central bank) by the forces of supply and demand, by what the market can bear. Since our money supply exists as an artificially scarce commodity, the creation of the vast majority of which is the monopoly of the private banking system, the market in bank credit can bear quite a bit and the resulting price that is charged for borrowing it is higher than it would be in a perfectly competitive market. The introduction of the Social Credit monetary reform would alter this dynamic in a number of crucial ways.[22]

As was recently explained by Wallace Klinck, all of the interest that is charged on the additional debt-money that is currently borrowed from private banks in the form of public, business, or consumer loans in order to bridge the recurring gap between prices and incomes (and which results in an ever-increasing mountain of societal debt that is, in the aggregate, unrepayable) is, from a Social Credit point of view, usurious by its very nature. The consuming public have a right in strict justice to the communal profit, i.e., the surplus of the consumer goods that the industrial economy yields over the consumer incomes that are distributed in the course of their production, without any conditions being imposed by the banking system or any other entity. We should be able to consume whatever we produce as a matter of course. If there is an inherent deficiency of consumer incomes with regard to what we produce, then the additional purchasing power necessary to achieve equilibrium should be automatically provided by the financial system in the form of money that is created free of debt or any other additional costs. In a Social Credit economy, this would be achieved by the National Dividend in conjunction with the compensated price. Hence it follows that if you eliminate the necessity for compensatory debts, you are eliminating ipso facto much of the long-term debt upon which compound interest (which increases exponentially over time) is currently charged. The Social Credit measures suspend the transfer of all of that wealth, privilege, and power over policy which the flow of compensatory debt-money renders possible ... a transfer which completely falls into the ‘illegitimate’ category and is therefore usurious.

So far so good. But, one may ask: what of the production loans that banks would continue to issue under Social Credit, especially long-term loans that may not be paid off for months or years? What kind of fees would the banks levy on such loans? Might ‘usury’ or the illegitimate transfer of purchasing power continue in a Social Credit economy unless some measures are explicitly taken to counteract the possibility?

In the first place, it should be noted that by keeping incomes and prices in perpetual balance, Social Credit would ensure that bank fees could never be onerous: whatever the banks charged there would always be sufficient consumer income to meet the corresponding fees. The only real concern, I think, is that bank fees on production loans may be excessive and, to that extent, exploitative. But what exactly would constitute ‘excessive’ charges in this case and what, if anything, should be done about it?

Apart from some vague statements that, under Social Credit, banks would charge ‘an equitable sum’ for certain services that they might render[23], I am not aware that Douglas addressed this particular issue in any thorough or rigorous manner.[24] Perhaps he believed that breaking the banks’ monopoly on credit-creation would, more or less automatically, lower the price of bank credit towards the market’s equilibrium point.

In any case, the suggestion that bank fees cannot or ought not to be determined by the free play of financial supply and demand (which would raise the price of loans to as high as the market can bear) but must be regulated so that profit is determined by turnover or volume is to be found in the writings of one of the most prominent of first-generation Social Crediters, Eric Butler:

As are all other businesses entitled to a profit for their services, so banks must be paid a reasonable remuneration for their administration of financial credit on behalf of the people. The cost of manufacturing bank credit is merely the amount of manpower, pens, ink and paper used [Butler is only dealing here with the cost of credit creation considered as an isolated operation, not with all of the many other legitimate costs which operating a bank involves – OH]. Even the London ‘Economist’ has suggested that a half per cent interest would be a liberal profit for the banks to make for the creation and administration of the people’s financial credit. If limited to a maximum of a half per cent interest charges, and if certain other principles of financial policy, which will be examined shortly, were applied, the profits of the banks would be governed by their turnover of business. Everyone with a knowledge of banking knows that there is no real competition in banking today, that bank amalgamation in every country have ensured an increasing and complete monopoly, and that this monopoly can only be broken by making banks directly responsible to the people as are other businesses. People must be in the position where they can penalise a bank not giving them the service they require by talking their business elsewhere. They must have an alternative. No bank will take another’s business today. If there were only one bank, as the nationalisers desire, and that subjected to control by the people now controlling the banking system, or similar people, the people would be in an even more intolerable position than they are now.[25]

I don’t know whether or not Butler’s suggestion that interest rates should be capped at a half per cent is a reasonable one given current economic conditions. Banks incur many legitimate costs and, in a Social Credit system, would remain in private hands and be run for profit – provided that their profit stems from exclusively serving a public or national financial policy rather than a self-serving policy of pecuniary gain at any and all costs.[26] Banks must be able to levy sufficiently high charges in order to cover these costs and to make functionalist profit possible.

There is, however, another way in which bank fees on production loans could be determined in a Social Credit Commonwealth. This new and alternative proposal is inspired by the perennial teaching of the Catholic Church on usury and is, at one and the same time, in complete conformity with Social Credit principles. As a matter of fact, the position on usury which is held by the Church could be inferred on a purely Social Credit basis.

According to the ‘fixed teaching on usury’ which was promulgated by Benedict XIV in the 1745 papal encyclical Vix Pervenit: http://www.papalencyclicals.net/Ben14/b14vixpe.htm, a position which claims for its authority both divine revelation and the testimony of human reason, the charging of interest on loans at any rate, or more broadly, the receipt of any amount of money over and above the sum lent, is intrinsically immoral if the basis upon which the claim is made is the loan contract itself.[27] In other words, and in complete accordance with statements made by previous ecumenical councils, earlier Popes, and the whole Christian tradition (up until the Protestant reformation), there is not, nor can there be, any intrinsic title or justification for “making money” on a loan. Unlike the renting of a physical good, such as a car, money does not lose part of its value or depreciate simply on account of its being used. However, and this is an important qualification which certain champions of the encyclical conveniently fail to either understand or to acknowledge, the encyclical simultaneously recognizes the legitimacy of extrinsic titles or justifications for receiving more than the sum that was lent. It does not specify what these extrinsic titles might be, but Church theologians have considered many possibilities: genuine risk, inflation, having to sacrifice one’s own legitimate needs in order to make the loan, having to forego guaranteed profits or lucrative investments in order to make the loan, having to sell assets in order to make the loan, and business operations are all real costs on the basis of which one can legitimately claim compensation from the borrower. Similarly, if one’s loan financed a productive undertaking, then it may rightly be regarded as an investment and a share in the profits (if there are profits) should be allocated to the lender. Within the context of an economy where prices and incomes were kept in an automatic and self-liquidating balance, receiving more money than was lent could only be considered usurious if what one received exceeded the extrinsic title in question and was therefore not proportionate to the claim.[28]

The basic justification for the Church’s position as presented in Vix Pervenit is that the principle of equity requires that there be an equality between what is lent and what is returned in order to ensure that no one party is taking advantage of the other or profiting at the other’s illegitimate expense. When one party gains more than the other from an exchange, the relationship is asymmetrical.

A concrete example should help to illustrate the injustice that is inherent in unbalanced exchanges. Assuming that production costs per pound are equal, if I give a pound of lettuce to a neighbouring farmer in the spring in exchange for a pound of carrots in the fall, then I should receive a pound of carrots from him in the fall in re-payment, not two or three pounds of carrots. The latter arrangement would qualify as an unequal and hence exploitative exchange. No one would agree to such terms unless he were forced to do so by circumstance. Now consider a monetary exchange involving the same values. If producing a pound of either carrots or lettuce costs one dollar, and I lend one dollar to the carrot farmer in the spring so that he can buy seed, I should, ceteris paribus, only receive one dollar back from him in the fall (or one pound of carrots) in repayment. If I insist, in the absence of any legitimate extrinsic title, on receiving two or three dollars in repayment, I am, in fact, asking for two or three pounds of carrots in exchange for having lent the monetary value of one pound of lettuce, a dollar that has only made the production of one pound of carrots possible. The exchange becomes unequal. Once again, no one would agree to such terms unless, practically speaking, he had no other choice.

The observance of the principle of equity in monetary exchanges contributes to harmonious and balanced interactions between people living in society and is necessary for social stability. It is, in fact, an application of what later thinkers would refer to as the principle of capitalist justice: a flourishing economy requires that exchanges approach the ideal of being equally mutually beneficial. Thus, as it is defined by the Church, usury cannot be identified with the simple charging of interest as such, but rather with the charging of interest or the receipt of more money than was lent under conditions which render the financial exchange fundamentally unequal or exploitative.

Extrinsic title is certainly present in the case of banking. As previously noted, banks have and, under Social Credit would continue to have, legitimate costs which must ultimately be covered by consumers in the fees that the banks levy. If the banks offered their services for free, consumers would be taking advantage of the bankers. There would be no equality in the exchange. Similarly, if, on account of their business acumen, the banks are careful to finance only those enterprises that are profitable, that deliver what a properly financed body of consumers living in a Social Credit commonwealth really want, then it is entirely appropriate for them to be recompensed by sharing in the profits that their lending decisions have made possible.

Though not intended as such, the teaching of the Church is simply one concrete application of the fundamental principle that would lie behind any Social Credit style monetary reform: ‘whatever we do in the financial realm should reflect, as accurately as possible, what is going on in the physical economic realm’. In the case of the Church’s teaching, a mirroring or accurate reflection on the financial plane of the physical facts which accompany financial exchanges involving loans is insisted on in order to ensure that equality is maintained in the exchange. Social Credit goes one step further and says that the whole financial system (not just contracts involving loans) must embody the principles of honest accounting; i.e., the financial system must accurately reflect the facts of the physical economy if it is to fulfill its true purpose.

In other words, it seems to me that acceptance of one of the arch-principles of Social Credit theory, i.e., that finance should always mirror reality, logically implies acceptance of the substance of the Church’s teaching regarding usury. Just as additions or subtractions to money should occur in accordance with additions or subtractions in the real credit if the financial credit is to be kept in harmony with the real credit, whenever money is lent what is returned should reflect or equal what is lent. An honest monetary system cannot admit dishonest profit, i.e., profit that cannot be justified in terms of either its nature or proportion on the basis of the relevant physical facts.

If finance accurately reflected reality in the realm of loan contracts, loans would be handled in this way: 1) if, in lending x number of dollars, the lender incurs a real cost, then the lender should be repaid the principal plus sufficient money to cover his legitimate costs to the extent of those costs; 2) if, in lending money to a business enterprise, that business yields a profit, it is entirely appropriate for the lender to receive an equitable share in the profits (as a fixed percentage agreed to at the time of the loan); and 3) if the lender’s activities do not involve a loss or a gain, then, in order to ensure that finance maintains its reflection of reality, the lender should recover his principal – no more or less. In sum, losses in lending should be compensated, honest profits made from lending shared, and, in the absence of either loss or gain, only the principal should be returned. By following these guidelines, the financial credit would maintain its mirroring of the facts of the real credit. The last stipulation is the linchpin of the whole approach because it guarantees that money would never be treated as a commodity but merely as a neutral, informational tool. The underlying idea is that money ought never to be used to make more money without simultaneously contributing something to the flow of real goods and services. Allowing money to make money independently of the real economy makes a mockery of money’s true purpose by preventing it from providing an accurate picture of the physical economic facts and causing it to deliver a distorted representation instead. There is, after all, no physical increase to parallel the increase in money that comes from lending money and demanding more in return merely on the basis of an alleged intrinsic title or justification.

Thus, it may be proposed that, in a Social Credit society, the standard fees that the private banks charge on production loans should be no more nor no less than what is necessary to cover their legitimate operating costs in providing said service. In principle, these fees may take the form of either interest or service fees – one can arrive at the same aggregate result regardless of the specific form that the fees assume – but, in my view, simple interest would be preferable over compound interest (since compound interest increases the fees exponentially over time, but there is no physical process to which this rate of increase in fees corresponds), while “service fees” would be psychologically and aesthetically preferable over “interest charges” since the former nomenclature makes it clear or reflects the fact that the banks are being paid for their book-keeping and other services and not for lending money as if it were a commodity. It may further be proposed that the banks obtain their profits by sharing in the risks of productive enterprises. That is, banks would be able to make a profit on their lending activities if and to the extent that they are successful in advancing credit to productive organizations that are actually profitable. The banks would share in these profits (when there are profits) on some equitable basis that would be agreed to as part of the loan contract. In order to increase their aggregate profits, private banks would have to compete with others for a larger share of the producer market.

The foregoing position on the question of bank fees certainly represents a development of Social Credit theory, but I would argue that it is a development which is entirely organic in character. I have merely made explicit what is implicit in the general Social Credit approach to financial and economic matters. Furthermore, I am convinced that this proposal or some other proposal along these lines, which is fair to all interested parties, would put the whole debate regarding usury, both within and outside of Social Credit circles, to rest once and for all.

 

 

 

Notes:

[1] Cf. John W. Hughes, Major DouglasThe Policy of a Philosophy (Edmonton, Alberta: Brightest Pebble Publishing, 2004), 3: “[U]sury was not the primary concern of Douglas, ... the actual ownership of the credit is the point at issue....” If it be recognized or once it is recognized that the rightful owners of the financial credit which the banking system administers are those who own, in varying degrees, the real credit, i.e., the common members of an economic association, then it naturally follows that the financial system should operate in their interests and not at their expense. A financial system that aimed to adequately reflect reality would automatically accord ownership of all financial credit and hence control over financial policy to the individual citizenry.


[2] One of the greatest difficulties in attempting to properly address the issue of usury lies in the fact that there are so many and by no means compatible definitions of ‘usury’ that have been put forward at different times by various thinkers. Usury has been identified with the charging of any rate of interest whatsoever on a loan, with the charging of exorbitant rates of interest on a loan, with the charging of interest on money created out of nothing (as opposed to the charging of interest on monies which the lender had legitimately earned), with the charging of interest on non-productive loans, such as loans for health care, education, or consumption generally (as opposed to productive loans, where the money lent is likely to generate a profit by financing business activities), and so forth. The definition of usury which is employed here, i.e., usury as ‘dishonest profit’ involving the illegitimate transfer of wealth, privilege, and power over policy from the common consumer to the proprietors of the banking system, cuts through the various definitions to get at the heart of the matter: under certain specified conditions the charging of interest on a loan or the receipt of more money that one lent may qualify as unjust or immoral because it constitutes a form of exploitation. As will become apparent later on in this essay, this more nuanced definition of usury can be regarded as both a Social Credit and a Catholic definition of the term.


[3] C.H. Douglas, Warning Democracy, 3rd ed. (London: Stanley Nott, 1935), 58.


[4] C.H. Douglas, The Control and Distribution of Production (London: Cecil Palmer, 1922), 28-29. That is, the banks administer the community’s financial credit primarily for their own benefit at the expense of the individual (to the extent that they fail to serve the best interests of individuals in an optimal manner, the banks are operating at the individual’s expense).


[5] C.H. Douglas, The Breakdown of the Employment System (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1979), 7.


[6] C.H. Douglas, The Monopoly of Credit, 4th ed. (Sudbury, England: Bloomfield Books, 1979), 17.


[7] C.H. Douglas, The Breakdown of the Employment System (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1979), 6.


[8] C.H. Douglas, Economic Democracy, 5th ed. (Sudbury, England: Bloomfield Books, 1974), 79.


[9] C.H. Douglas, “Money: An Historical Survey,” The Fig Tree, no. 2 (September 1936): 146.


[10] C.H. Douglas, Dictatorship by Taxation (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 6-7.


[11] C.H. Douglas, Warning Democracy, 3rd ed. (London: Stanley Nott, 1935), 34. [emphasis mine].


[12] C.H. Douglas, Major C.H. Douglas before the New Zealand Government’s Monetary Committee (Auckland: Dawson Printing Co. LTD., 1934), 12 [emphasis mine]. On page 13 of the same document Douglas clarified his statement by noting that “circumstances have put these organisations [i.e., the banks – OH] into a position in which, whether they have a conscious desire or not, they are in fact in the position of the recipients of unjustifiable wealth.”


[13] C.H. Douglas,The New and the Old Economics (Sydney: Tidal Publications, 1973), 12-13.


[14] C.H. Douglas, Dictatorship by Taxation (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 11., 6. [emphasis mine] Cf. C.H. Douglas, Money and the Price System (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 7:

“[T]axation in Great Britain is … twice as heavy as that in any other country in the world – more than half of its taxation is in connection with what are called national debts, war loans, consols and things of that kind. If you investigate the facts as to the ownership of these world debts and war loans you will find them preponderantly held by large financial institutions. You have at once a very good business reason for large quantities of taxation if half of it goes to the service of national loans which are held by large financial institutions: that, as an ordinary business proposition, is obvious. It is still more obvious when you consider that these debts were actually created in the first place by financial institutions, by lending of that money to governments, and the receiving in return of large blocks of national securities which the financial institutions receive for nothing.”


[15] C.H. Douglas, Tyranny (London: Social Credit Secretariat Ltd., 1936), 1.


[16] C.H. Douglas, Dictatorship by Taxation (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 9.


[17] C.H. Douglas, The Monopoly of Credit, 4th ed.(Sudbury, England: Bloomfield Books, 1979), 73-74.


[18] C.H. Douglas, Dictatorship by Taxation (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 7.


[19] C.H. Douglas, Money and the Price System (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 8.


[20] C.H. Douglas, Major C.H. Douglas Speaks (Sydney: Douglas Social Credit Association, 1933), 59.


[21] Cf. C.H. Douglas, Warning Democracy, 3rd ed. (London: Stanley Nott, 1935), 99-100.


[22] Indeed, if usury is defined as dishonest profit, Social Credit would qualify as a ‘usury-free’ money system, but, it must not be forgotten that this anti-usury feature is not the main benefit or aim of a Social Credit monetary reform. Social Credit is so much more than a system that would disallow exploitative banking practices. It is, in fact, the monetary system which would finally enable the economy to fulfill its true purpose: the delivery of goods and services, as, when and where required, with the least amount of trouble to everyone. The focus of the Social Credit monetary reform is on maximizing individual benefit, not on merely eliminating certain evils of the existing system.


[23] In his ‘Draft Social Credit Scheme for Scotland’ Douglas stipulated that the banks should acquire sufficient credit to cover the cost of administering the price discounts to businesses via reasonable service fees: “The existing banks will be empowered to charge an equitable sum for the services thus rendered.” C.H. Douglas, Social Credit, rev. ed. (New York: Gordon Press, 1973), 210.


[24] It may be that Douglas did in fact deal effectively with this question at some point in time. There are many addresses, articles, etc., which are recorded in the earliest Social Credit publications (Social Credit, The Social Crediter, The Fig Tree, etc.) which I have not yet read.


[25] Eric Butler, The Truth about Social Credit (Happy Valley: South Australia, 1993), 11. This proposal is quite similar to Douglas’ idea that, as part of the compensated price mechanism, retail profits would have to be regulated (not fixed) to an agreed percentage on turnover. Cf. C.H. Douglas, Major C.H. Douglas Speaks (Sydney: Douglas Social Credit Association, 1933), 96: "The conditions of such registration will be that their accounts ... should contain an additional item showing the average profit on turnover, and that their prices shall, as far as practicable, be maintained at a figure to include such average profit, where this is agreed as equitable for the type of business concerned (the suitable profit being, of course, largely dependent on the velocity of turn-over)."


[26] The reader will note that Social Credit is firmly opposed to nationalizing the banking system. Cf. C.H. Douglas, Money and the Price System (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 13: "I am not myself, for instance, an advocate of the nationalisation of banks. I believe this again to be one of those misapprehensions so common in regard to these matters, for the nationalisation of banks is merely an administrative change: it does not mean a change in policy, and a mere administrative change cannot be expected to produce any result whatever in regard to this matter. A change in monetary policy can be made without interfering with the administration or ownership of a single bank in the world; and if it could be got into the heads of the comparatively few people who control these enormous monetary institutions that they would lose nothing but power – and that they will lose that power anyway – the thing would be achieved." Cf. also, C.H. Douglas, Dictatorship by Taxation (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 7: “No nationalization of banking will put one penny into the hands of the individuals comprising the countries over whom it rules, so long as this question of the ownership of money is left unaltered. But if it once be admitted that the community, not its Government, is the owner of the money, and the individual, as part of the community, is entitled to his share of it, the situation is obviously very different.”


At one and the same time, however, it must be clearly understood that, under Social Credit, the private banks would not function as ordinary businesses which are exclusively concerned with maximizing profits. They would be recompensed in exchange for effectively serving a public policy. Cf., C.H. Douglas, Major C.H. Douglas before the New Zealand Government’s Monetary Committee (Auckland: Dawson Printing Co. LTD., 1934), 15: “[T]he banking system at the present time seems to oscillate between the suggestion that it is an ordinary business concern with the sole object of making profits and that it is not an ordinary business concern but is identified with the general interests of the whole community. Now, if you take the second point of view, with which fundamentally I would agree, that it cannot be considered at all as an ordinary business simply concerned with making profits, the answer to your question is that it is desirable in the general interests that it should take on that business.”

Cf. also: C.H. Douglas, “Major Douglas at Dunedin (N.Z.),” The Social Credit Standard, no. 9 (July-August, 1934): 9-10: "I had a talk with a very pleasant and kind and, indeed, eminently respectable bank man-ager in Wellington, quite accidentally, a week or two ago on quite ordinary matters. The conversation turned on the banking system, and he claimed that the banking system was a business like any other business, and that it was run in order to make a profit like any other business, and that the sole consideration that it had in mind was to carry it on along the successful lines of any other business.
Well, I do not know whether that is an idea which is prevalent amongst all bankers. But if it is then it is the final condemnation of the banking system as it stands at the present time, because it is quite obvious that something which interpenetrates and controls the activities of the wealth-producing organisation on which we all live, cannot possibly, whether it is privately administered or whether it is publicly administered is not the point--but it cannot be run as a private interest. That is incredible. It simply means that everybody's business is at the mercy of this private organisation, and we know that it is."

To this end, Douglas argued that bankers should be licensed and that the creation of credit for production should be publicly controlled although its issuance would not be publicly administered:

"[T]he chairmen, superior officials, and branch managers of all banks, insurance companies, and other financial institutions should, as is the case with smaller pawnbrokers, be licensed. The fee for such a licence should be moderate (say £ 100) if the individual retained his post indefinitely. For every change in the personnel within a period of, say, five years, not due to death or disability, a very substantial increase in the licence should be imposed. The general policy to be pursued by finance should then be imposed by Parliament, and no interference with the details of banking, insurance or other finance be permitted.

If the policy imposed by Parliament is not achieved within a reasonable time, a sufficient number of chairmen and other officials of financial institutions should have their licences withdrawn, and the very greatly enhanced fees (I would suggest 1,000 times the original licence) exacted for the new licences should be applied to the reduction of general taxation.

I have no doubt whatever that some such policy as this would brighten the brains of bankers who are unable to see any way out of our present difficulties." C.H. Douglas, The Tragedy of Human Effort (Vancouver: The Institute of Economic Democracy, 1978), 9.

Cf. C.H. Douglas, The Monopoly of Credit, 4th ed. (Sudbury, England: Bloomfield Books, 1979), 147:

“In the future attempts which will be made to give effect to such propositions as the foregoing, it will be necessary carefully to distinguish between the private administration of credit as a public property and what is commonly called ‘public administration,’ it being quite probable that the former is in every way preferable as a means of administration.”

Cf. C.H. Douglas, “Authoritative Democracy,” The Douglas Social Credit Advocate 1, no. v (January 1935): 3. "Unless we are profoundly mistaken, we believe that such a system would involve three main characteristics. First, a scientific regulation of prices, secondly, the public control, though not necessarily the public administration, of the creation of credit for production, and thirdly, the distribution of an increasing and universal National Dividend, so that every British born subject would become a shareholder in Great Britain, and, perhaps, ultimately, in the British Empire." (emphasis mine)


[27] Interestingly enough, this encyclical remains widely unknown in Catholic circles, and, in the pre-internet era, copies of it were very difficult to obtain.


[28] Since, under the current system, no direct attempt is made to compensate for the inherent sterility of money, i.e., the fact that lending money cannot, by itself, breed more money with which the interest charge might be paid (as many philosophers such as Aristotle, St. Thomas Aquinas, and Jacques Maritain have noted), it is doubtful whether, as a matter of fact (as opposed to principle), any and all extrinsic justifications could be sufficient, under existing conditions, to restore full equality to monetary exchanges.

Last modified on Friday, 23 March 2018 08:59
More in this category: « Social Credit and Usury

Leave a comment

Make sure you enter all the required information, indicated by an asterisk (*). HTML code is not allowed.

12 comments

  • Comment Link Oliver Monday, 20 December 2021 18:14 posted by Oliver

    You're most welcome and thank you, Pedro! I wish you a very Merry Christmas and a Happy New Year as well. God bless you.

  • Comment Link Pedro Friday, 17 December 2021 05:01 posted by Pedro

    Thank you Oliver

    Thank you for your willingness to help me with my doubts.

    I wish you a happy Christmas and peace with God. Hugs

  • Comment Link Oliver Thursday, 16 December 2021 17:32 posted by Oliver

    Hi Pedro,

    Thanks for your feedback and questions! Yes, so if someone lends money and they incur a cost in doing so, then it would only be just for the borrower to compensate the lender for his loss. Otherwise, the borrower would be taking advantage of the lender ... well, in reality, the lender would stop lending entirely if he had to lend at a constant loss.

    When it comes to banks, banks have to pay for employees, supplies, equipment, utilities, locations to rent, etc., in order to provide their various services. They therefore would be entitled to charge their customers enough to meet those costs. Bank profits could be governed by a share of the profit in the business that they lend to as a reward for making good lending decisions.

    When it comes to entrepreneurs or businesses in general, the profit that serves as the minimum incentive to produce is an appropriate reward for the risk, time, effort, and skills involved for innovation, organizing new production, seeking out markets, etc. Theoretically, they would get the reward, the profit, if they serve consumer demand well and fail to get it if they serve consumer demand poorly or inappropriately. Profit thus serves as an important feedback mechanism. Provided it is proportionate and arises within the context of a perfectly competitive market, it is a just and efficient tool for a functional economy.

  • Comment Link Pedro Tuesday, 14 December 2021 17:45 posted by Pedro

    Hi Oliver,

    This article has really added some knowledge to me about usury.

    From what I understand, if the loan causes you any kind of cost then it is lawful for the lender to charge a fee.

    "if, in lending x number of dollars, the lender incurs a real cost, then the lender should be repaid the principal plus sufficient money to cover his legitimate costs to the extent of those costs."

    I ask you the following questions:

    Does the loan that banks make today entail any type of cost? What types?

    If the bank, when obtaining a cost for the loan it made, can charge a consumer fee that is only equal to the value of this cost, no more than that, why should the entrepreneur have the right to charge the consumer a price that exceeds its costs?

  • Comment Link Danial Thursday, 24 May 2018 18:20 posted by Danial

    I'm not ѕure why bսt this web site is loading incredibly slow fօr
    me. Iѕ anyone elsе havіng this issue or is it a issue on mу end?
    I'll check bacҝ lɑter on and ѕee if the problеm stilⅼ exists.

  • Comment Link Charlene Friday, 18 May 2018 20:56 posted by Charlene

    Oһ my goodness! Incredible article dude! Ƭhanks, Howeνer I am goіng through troubles witһ үour RSS.
    Ι don?t understand thе reason why I cannot subscribe
    tо it. Іѕ there anybody else getting tһe same RSS issues?
    Аnybody who knows tһe solution ᴡill үou kindly respond?
    Ꭲhanx!!

  • Comment Link Joe Friday, 26 January 2018 15:11 posted by Joe

    I have thought about the subject of usury a "lot" in the past years. Although I can agree with most of what has been presented thus far, I have a problem when a finger is pointed at a "thing" rather than a person. Corporations, the Stock Market, the Federal Reserve, and even Usury are just things. The real problem IMO reside within man himself. We are our own enemy. Unfortunately most don't know it yet. When I found this out it, I was very angry at myself. People are causing their own suffering, and the suffering of others, and have no clue they are doing. These are the ones who need to be confronted. I never did anything over the interenet but I started my own free page EconomicMind.jimdo.com to try to tell this story that goes so deep. Please let me know if I should continue.

  • Comment Link  Oliver Heydorn Friday, 26 January 2018 15:10 posted by Oliver Heydorn

    Thank you, Ted, for your comment. Yes, usury, defined as dishonest profit, is not the underlying or most important problem with the existing financial system. But the mere bank creation of the money supply is not, as such, the fundamental problem either. The fundamental problem is the use of bank created money in favour of a self-serving policy on the part of the banks in place of that policy which would best serve the interests of the common citizen. The present financial policy delivers the least amount of goods to us in exchange for the greatest amount of effort from us (as measured in gains in wealth, power, and privilege for the banking system), whereas the Social Credit financial policy would deliver the greatest amount of goods with the least amount of effort on the part of the common individual. One can imagine a consumer-friendly financial system that still employs the bank creation of credit. One can also imagine a consumer-hostile financial system that employs the government creation of money. Someone has to create the money supply. The key issue is who controls the money that is created: the individuals who make up society or an oligarchic elite? Who determines policy?

  • Comment Link  Theodore Reznowski Friday, 26 January 2018 15:09 posted by Theodore Reznowski

    Thanks for this topic. I recently was discussing this with someone. They were right in stating that usury was not the main problem, but I argued that most of us personally feel the great sting of usury from a loan, in our own lives as the great "personal" injustice of the present system. True, the greater fraud and negative effect on society is money creation by the banks itself, which Social Credit would reform. But a usurious loan to a family, with compound interest, with repayment many times the original amount, is the personal tragedy of the present system. We become truly life-long servants to private banking interests, many working their whole lives, unable to repay their mortgage, and other financial debts. A usurious loan--the injustice that destroys family peace of mind. But yes, caused ultimately by the greater fraud--bank created money.

  • Comment Link  dr faiz khan Friday, 26 January 2018 15:09 posted by dr faiz khan

    nice essay - although if a money lender entitles himself to the profits of an enterprise with the agreement of the producer , this is no longer a loan, it is an investment...which means the investor (not the lender must also suffer loss, if such ensues.)
    The so called "Islamic" banking sector has made use of these theories, but the result is still usurious - because the "fees" charged, are in the aggregate similar to what a producer would be paying under compound interest. It is essentially putting lipstick on a pig.
    This issue is really not that complicated - and correct implementation derives from a proper understanding of what the properties of the entity we call money are and are NOT. The only characteristic that all of the world's Sacred traditions insist upon is that humans never implement the idea that a moneyed person - just by virtue of making a loan, feel entitled that solely by virtue of the time his principal was remained away from him,- that he demand that any increase be returned to him. The extrinsic factors mentioned above are obvious points - and indeed no fair minded person would argue against personnel of a monetary system receiving fair wages for their services - in the same fashion that no one would argue personnel of the postal service or power companies receive a just wage for their services.

  • Comment Link KingofthePaupers Friday, 26 January 2018 15:08 posted by KingofthePaupers

    As I tried to show in my recent blog entry on “Social Credit and Usury”: http://www.socred.org/blogs/view/social-credit-and-usury, the claim that usury (however defined) is THE problem and that Social Credit means nothing more than “usury-free money” is a serious but all too common misrepresentation of the Social Credit diagnosis and remedial proposals.
    Jct: Sorry but eliminating the positive feedback in the 1/(s-i) usury ("i") bank account provides a stable 1/s account proven by LETS timebank currencies. http://johnturmel.com/bankmath has the math.

  • Comment Link  Jean-Nil Chabot Friday, 26 January 2018 15:07 posted by Jean-Nil Chabot

    Oui, un excellent cours de politique douglasienne, mais pour chercher à le comprendre et ensuite l'apprécier il faudra peut-être une absolue nécessité - il faudra peut-être que le système absurde actuel s'écroule. Et je crois, en effet, que le système actuel va un jour s'écrouler. Pourquoi? Parce que le seul créateur de l'argent ne peut demander en retour plus qu'il ne crée. C'est ce qui fait que les dettes nationales ne peuvent pas être remboursées. A, (l'argent emprunté) ne peut égaler A + B (B= l'intérêt). (Un cousin du théorem a+b de Douglas qui visait le désaccord entre le pouvoir d'achat et le coût de production.) Au cas où les banques continueraient dans leur rôle de créer l'argent elles mériteraient une rémunération qui devrait être puisée dans l'argent qu'elles auraient déjà créée. Bien entendu, ce paiement ne pourrait pas être répété comme c'est le cas pour l'intérêt. Il s'en suivrait que A+B = A+B. D'accord?

Latest Articles

  • Douglas Social Credit ... By Way Of Metaphor
    For whatever reason, Douglas Social Credit seems to exhibit an unusually high informational “barrier to entry” and yet it is vital that as many people as possible would come to understand it as quickly as possible because the financial analysis and remedial proposals of Major C.H. Douglas (1879-1952) are the solution to 90% or more of our financial, economic, political, cultural, environmental, and international problems. In what follows, I will focus on the monetary dimensions of Douglas Social Credit, though the reader should be aware that DSC constitutes a much broader body of thought which incorporates a social philosophy, a political theory, and also a theory of history. Since the easiest way to grasp something new and therefore unknown is to approach it by means of the known, this article relies heavily on metaphors to communicate the truth of Douglas’ vision.
    Written on Saturday, 13 January 2024 15:56 Read more...
  • Dr. Oliver Heydorn on Mark Anderson's "Stop the Presses" Radio Show
    On January 3rd, 2024 and again on January 10th, 2024, Dr. Oliver Heydorn appeared as a guest of Journalist Mark Anderson on the Republican Broadcasting Network. The interviews can be accessed under "read more".
    Written on Wednesday, 10 January 2024 17:02 Read more...
  • Inflation? Maybe it’s Time We Tried Compensated Price Discounts
    If the inflation we are witnessing is cost-push, instead of demand-pull, or insofar as it is cost-push, there is another way of dealing with the problem which governments and their central banks should seriously consider: compensated price discounts. Instead of increasing wages across the board (which will only further increase prices), the same amount of money required for the wage increases could be spent on reducing prices through a universally applied discount (a kind of reverse sales tax). Retailers would be compensated to the extent of the discount (enabling them to meet their costs in full), while consumers would see the purchasing power of their current wages, savings, etc., correspondingly increased. The cost-push inflation would be neutralized and everyone would benefit.
    Written on Friday, 05 August 2022 00:40 Read more...